Vol. 3 No. 1 (2023): Space
Miscellaneous

The Role of Errors in Fallibilist Theories of Knowledge

Dániel Golden
Research Centre for the Humanities

Published 2023-07-27

Keywords

  • fallibilism,
  • epistemology,
  • philosophy of science,
  • refutation,
  • trial and error

How to Cite

Golden, D. (2023). The Role of Errors in Fallibilist Theories of Knowledge. Papers in Arts and Humanities, 3(1), 129–140. https://doi.org/10.52885/pah.v3i1.135

Abstract

Fallibilism in epistemology is the view that we as human beings can never be in the position of acquiring ultimate truth, there is always a chance for discovering that we were in error. Nevertheless, fallibilists are not sceptics: they still stick to the idea that we are always in the position of holding a set of temporary truths, prevalent until the moment of getting denied and replaced by a better or more attractive candidate. On the other hand, fallibilists do side with the sceptics in their opposition to dogmatics, since they do not find compelling closed systems of knowledge, as they plea constantly for genuinely new insights.

According to the presented fallibilist models of knowledge, trials are necessary steps in acquiring new knowledge; there is no growth of knowledge without exercising the practice of trial and error. Errors are the necessary components of the procedure, since the usability of deductive and inductive methods getting to necessary truths in real life are strongly limited. In practice alternative strategies, like abductive reasoning, are coming to the front in our pursuit for maintainable propositions.

References

  1. Cowles, H. M. (2015). Hypothesis bound: Trial and error in the nineteenth century. Isis, 106(3), 635–645.
  2. Haack, S. (1979). Fallibilism and necessity. Synthese, 41(1), 37–63.
  3. Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press.
  4. Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34(3), 503–533.
  5. Kuhn, Th. S. (1977). The logic of discovery or psychology of research. In: Th. S. Kuhn, The essential tension (pp. 266–292). University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1970)
  6. Lakatos, I. (1974). The role of crucial experiments in science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, Part A, 4(4), 309–325.
  7. Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. The logic of mathematical discovery. J. Worrall & E. Zahar (Eds.), Cambridge University Press.
  8. Marchi, P. (1980). Intellectual maps. Philosophy of the Social Sciences. 10(4), 445–458.
  9. Margolis, J. (1998). Peirce’s fallibilism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 34(3), 535–569.
  10. Paavola, S. (2006). On the origin of ideas: An abductivist approach to discovery. University of Helsinki.
  11. Peirce, C. S. (1960). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. 5. Pragmatism and pragmaticism, vol. 6. Scientific metaphysics. C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds). Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1931)
  12. Polya, G. (1971). How to solve it. A new aspect of mathematical method. Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1945)
  13. Popper, K. R. (1963). What is dialectic? In: K. R. Popper, Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge (pp. 312–335). Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original work published 1940)
  14. Popper, K. R. (1963). Science: Conjectures and refutations. In: K. R. Popper, Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge (pp. 33–65). Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original work published 1957)
  15. Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford University Press.
  16. Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107(2), 143–157. Walton, D. (2004). Abductive reasoning. University of Alabama Press.